text
stringlengths 0
80
|
---|
Objection 3: Further, he that has virtue performs works of virtue with |
ease and pleasure: wherefore the Philosopher says (Ethic. i, 8) that |
"a man is not just if he does not rejoice in just deeds." Now many |
penitents find difficulty in performing deeds of virtue. Therefore |
the virtues are not restored through Penance. |
Contrary: We read (Luke 15:22) that the father commanded his |
penitent son to be clothed in "the first robe," which, according to |
Ambrose (Expos. in Luc. vii), is the "mantle of wisdom," from which |
all the virtues flow together, according to Wis. 8:7: "She teacheth |
temperance, and prudence, and justice, and fortitude, which are such |
things as men can have nothing more profitable in life." Therefore |
all the virtues are restored through Penance. |
Response: Sins are pardoned through Penance, as stated above |
(Q. 86, A. 1). But there can be no remission of sins except through |
the infusion of grace. Wherefore it follows that grace is infused |
into man through Penance. Now all the gratuitous virtues flow from |
grace, even as all the powers result from the essence of the soul; as |
stated in the Second Part (I-II, Q. 110, A. 4, ad 1). Therefore all |
the virtues are restored through Penance. |
Reply Objection 1: Penance restores the virtues in the same way as it |
causes grace, as stated above (Q. 86, A. 1). Now it is a cause of |
grace, in so far as it is a sacrament, because, in so far as it is a |
virtue, it is rather an effect of grace. Consequently it does not |
follow that penance, as a virtue, needs to be the cause of all the |
other virtues, but that the habit of penance together with the habits |
of the other virtues is caused through the sacrament of Penance. |
Reply Objection 2: In the sacrament of Penance human acts stand as matter, |
while the formal power of this sacrament is derived from the power of |
the keys. Consequently the power of the keys causes grace and virtue |
effectively indeed, but instrumentally; and the first act of the |
penitent, viz., contrition, stands as ultimate disposition to the |
reception of grace, while the subsequent acts of Penance proceed from |
the grace and virtues which are already there. |
Reply Objection 3: As stated above (Q. 86, A. 5), sometimes after the |
first act of Penance, which is contrition, certain remnants of sin |
remain, viz. dispositions caused by previous acts, the result being |
that the penitent finds difficulty in doing deeds of virtue. |
Nevertheless, so far as the inclination itself of charity and of the |
other virtues is concerned, the penitent performs works of virtue |
with pleasure and ease, even as a virtuous man may accidentally find |
it hard to do an act of virtue, on account of sleepiness or some |
indisposition of the body. |
_______________________ |
SECOND ARTICLE [III, Q. 89, Art. 2] |
Whether, After Penance, Man Rises Again to Equal Virtue? |
Objection 1: It would seem that, after Penance, man rises again to |
equal virtue. For the Apostle says (Rom. 8:28): "To them that love |
God all things work together unto good," whereupon a gloss of |
Augustine says that "this is so true that, if any such man goes |
astray and wanders from the path, God makes even this conduce to his |
good." But this would not be true if he rose again to lesser virtue. |
Therefore it seems that a penitent never rises again to lesser virtue. |
Objection 2: Further, Ambrose says [*Cf. Hypognosticon iii, an anonymous |
work falsely ascribed to St. Augustine] that "Penance is a very good |
thing, for it restores every defect to a state of perfection." But |
this would not be true unless virtues were recovered in equal |
measure. Therefore equal virtue is always recovered through Penance. |
Objection 3: Further, on Gen. 1:5: "There was evening and morning, one |
day," a gloss says: "The evening light is that from which we fall; |
the morning light is that to which we rise again." Now the morning |
light is greater than the evening light. Therefore a man rises to |
greater grace or charity than that which he had before; which is |
confirmed by the Apostle's words (Rom. 5:20): "Where sin abounded, |
grace did more abound." |
Contrary: Charity whether proficient or perfect is greater |
than incipient charity. But sometimes a man falls from proficient |
charity, and rises again to incipient charity. Therefore man always |
rises again to less virtue. |
Response: As stated above (Q. 86, A. 6, ad 3; Q. 89, A. 1, ad |
2), the movement of the free-will, in the justification of the |
ungodly, is the ultimate disposition to grace; so that in the same |
instant there is infusion of grace together with the aforesaid |
movement of the free-will, as stated in the Second Part (I-II, Q. |
113, AA. 5, 7), which movement includes an act of penance, as stated |
above (Q. 86, A. 2). But it is evident that forms which admit of |
being more or less, become intense or remiss, according to the |
different dispositions of the subject, as stated in the Second Part |
(I-II, Q. 52, AA. 1, 2; Q. 66, A. 1). Hence it is that, in Penance, |
according to the degree of intensity or remissness in the movement of |
the free-will, the penitent receives greater or lesser grace. Now the |
intensity of the penitent's movement may be proportionate sometimes |
to a greater grace than that from which man fell by sinning, |
sometimes to an equal grace, sometimes to a lesser. Wherefore the |
penitent sometimes arises to a greater grace than that which he had |
before, sometimes to an equal, sometimes to a lesser grace: and the |
same applies to the virtues, which flow from grace. |
Reply Objection 1: The very fact of falling away from the love of God by |